Time and Alternity by Computer Hans Moravec The Robotics Institute Carnegie-Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 (412) 268-3829 Copyright 1986 by Hans P. Moravec Time travel is a familiar concept in science fiction, and often brings with it the concept of alternate worlds. The mechanism of time travel is usually some extrapolation of modern physics - certainly fertile ground, with special relativity allowing communication to the past if faster than light particles could be found, general relativity allowing spacetime to be warped and twisted into temporal knots, and quantum mechanics seemingly founded on the temporary superposition of alternate worlds. Yet, if tachyons really don't exist, if Tipler vortex time machines are in principle impossible to build and black holes lead only to oblivion, if the alternate worlds in quantum mechanics are a mere mathematical artefact, or are truly inacessible, are we stuck, helplessly drifting down the one way river of time? Is there some way out, other than exotic physics? Here's how to do it with a philosophical leap and a lot of conventional future technology. \sect{What Am I?} Let's suppose we have some method of reading out the contents of a human mind into a computer controlling a robotic body, in such a way that the machine behaves like the person it absorbed. Science fiction readers have encountered this concept many times, but often the stories and articles have been humorous in tone, masking, I think, a discomfort with the idea felt even by the authors. This feeling is sometimes articulated in statements like: ``Regardless of how the copying is done the end result will be a new person. If it is I who am being copied, the copy, though it may think of itself as me, is simply a self-deluded imposter. If the copying process destroys the original then I have been killed. That the copy may then have a good time using my name and my skills is no comfort to my mortal remains.'' This point of view, which I will call the {\it Body Identity} position, makes a mockery of many of the supposed advantages of being ``mind transferred'' to a new body. I believe the objection can and should be overcome by intellectual acceptance of an alternate position I will name {\it Pattern Identity}. Body identity assumes that a person is defined by the stuff of which a human body is made. Only by maintaining continuity of body stuff can we preserve an individual person. Pattern identity, on the other hand, defines the essence of a person, say myself, as the {\it pattern} and the {\it process} going on in my head and body, not the machinery supporting that process. If the process is preserved, I am preserved. The rest is mere jelly. \sect{Matter Transmitters} Matter transmitters have appeared often in the science fiction literature, at least since the invention of facsimile machines in the late 1800s. I raise the idea here only as a thought experiment, to simplify some of the issues in the mind transfer proposal of. A facsimile transmitter scans a photograph line by line with a light sensitive photocell, and produces an electric current that varies with the brightness of the scanned point in the picture. The varying electric current is transmitted over wires to a remote location where it controls the brightness of a light bulb in a facsimile receiver. The receiver scans the bulb over photosensitive paper in the same pattern as the transmitter. When this paper is developed, a duplicate of the original photograph is obtained. This device was a boon to newspapers, who were able to get illustrations from remote parts of the country almost instantly, rather than after a period of days by train. If pictures, why not solid objects? A {\it matter transmitter} might scan an object and identify, then knock out, its atoms or molecules one at a time. The identity of the atoms would be transmitted to a receiver where a duplicate of the original object would be assembled in the same order from a local supply of atoms. The technical problems were mind boggling, and well beyond anything foreseeable, but the principle was simple to grasp. If solid objects, why not a person? Just stick him in the transmitter, turn on the scan, and greet him when he walks from the receiver. But is it really the same person? If the system works well, the duplicate will be indistinguishable from the original in any substantial way. Yet, suppose you fail to turn on the receiver during the transmission process. The transmitter will scan and disassemble the victim, and send an unheard message to the inoperative receiver. The original person will be dead. Doesn't, in fact, the process kill the original person whether or not there is an active receiver? Isn't the duplicate just that, merely a clever imposter? Or suppose two receivers respond to the message from one transmitter. Which, if either, of the two duplicates is the real original? \sect{Pattern Identity} The body identity position is clear. A matter transmitter is an execution device. You might as well save your money and use a gas chamber, and not be taken in by the phony double gimmick. Pattern identity gives a different perspective. Suppose I step into the transmission chamber. The transmitter scans and disassembles my jelly-like body, but my pattern (me!) moves continuously from the dissolving jelly, through the transmitting beam, and ends up in other jelly at the destination. At no instant was it (I) ever destroyed. The biggest confusion comes from the question of duplicates. It is rooted in all our past experience that one person corresponds to one body. In the light of the possibility of matter and mind storage and transmission this simple, natural, and obvious identification becomes confusing and misleading. Suppose the matter transmitter is connected to two receivers instead of one. After the transfer there will be a copy of you in each one. Surely at least one of them is a mere copy - they can't both be you, right? {\it Wrong!} Consider the message ``I am not jelly''. As I type it it goes from my brain, into the keyboard of my computer, through myriads of electronic circuits and over great amounts of wire, and after countless adventures shows up in bunches of books like the one you're holding. How many messages were there? I claim it is most useful to think there is only one, despite its massive replication. If I repeat it here: ``I am not jelly'', there is still only one message. Only if I change it in a significant manner: ``I am not peanut butter'' do we have a second message. And the message is not destroyed until the last written version is lost, and until it fades sufficiently in everybody's memory to be unreconstructable. The message is the information conveyed, not the particular encoding. The ``pattern and process'' that I claim is the real me has the same properties as the message above. Making a momentary copy of my state, whether on tape or in another functional body, doesn't make two persons. There is a complication because of the ``process'' aspect; as soon as an instance of a ``person message'' evolves for a while it becomes a different person. If two of them are active, they will diverge, and become two different people by my definition. Just how far this differentiation must proceed before you grant them unique identities is about as problematical as the question ``when does a fetus becomes a person?'' But if you wait zero time, then you don't have a new person. If, in the dual receiver version of the matter transmitter, you allow the two copies to be made and kill one (either one) instantly on reception, the transmitted person still exists in the other copy. All the things that person might have done, and all the thoughts she might have thought, are still possible. If, on the other hand, you allow both copies to live their separate lives for a year, and then kill one, you are the murderer of a unique human being. {\it But}, if you wait only a short while, they won't differ by much, and destruction of one won't cause too much total loss. This rationale might, for instance, be a comfort in danger if you knew that a tape backup copy of you had been made recently. Because of the divergence the tape contains not you as you are now, but you as you were: a slightly different person. Still, most of you would be saved should you have a fatal accident, and the loss would be nowhere near as great as without the backup. Intellectual acceptance that a secure and recent backup of you exists does not necessarily protect you from an instinctive self-preservation overreaction if faced with imminent death. This is an evolutionary hangover from your one-copy past. It is no more a reflection of reality than fear of flying is an appropriate response to present airline accident rates. Inappropriate intuitions are to be expected when the rules of life are suddenly reversed from historical absolutes. \sect{Soul in Abstraction} Although we've reasoned from strictly reductionistic assumptions about the nature of thought and self, the pattern identity position has clear dualistic implications. Though mind is entirely the consequence of interacting matter, the ability to copy it from one machine or storage medium to another gives it an independence and an identity apart from its machinery. The dualism is especially apparent if we consider some of the variations of encoding possible. Some supercomputer designs call for myriads of individual computers interconnected by a network that allows free flow of information among them. An operating system for this arrangement might allow individual processes to migrate from one processor to another in mid computation, in a kind of juggling act that permits more processes than there are processors. If a human mind is installed in a future machine of this variety, functions originally performed by particular cell assemblies might be encoded in individual processes. The juggling action would ensure that operations occurring in fixed areas in the original brain would move rapidly from place to place within the machine. If the computer is running other programs besides the mind simulation, then the simulation might find itself shuffled into entirely different sets of processors from moment to moment. The thinking process would be uninterrupted, even as its location and physical machinery changed continuously, because the immaterial pattern would keep its continuity. A process that is described as a long sequence of steps can sometimes be transformed mathematically into one that arrives a the same conclusion in far fewer operations. As a young boy the famous mathematician Friedrich Gauss was a school smartaleck. As a diversion a teacher once set him the problem of adding up the all the numbers between $1$ and $100$. He returned with the correct answer in less than a minute. He had noticed that the hundred numbers could be grouped onto fifty pairs, $1+100$, $2+99$, $3+98$, $4+97$ and so on, each pair adding up to $101$. Fifty times $101$ is $5,050$, the answer, found without a lot of tedious addition. Similar speedups are possible in complex processes. So called {\it optimizing compilers} have repertoires of accelerating transformations, some very radical, to streamline programs they translate. The key may be a total reorganization in the order of the computation and the representation of the data. A very powerful class of transformations takes an array of values and combines them in different ways to produce another array. Each final value reflects all the original values, and each original value affects all the results. An operation on a single transformed quantity can substitute for a whole host of operations on the original array, and enormous efficiencies are possible. Analogous transformations in time also work: a sequence of operations is changed into an equivalent one where each new step does a tiny fraction of the work of every one of the original steps. The localized is diffused, and the diffuse is localized. A program can quickly be altered beyond recognition by a few mathematical rewrites of this power. Run on a multiprocessor, single events in the original formulation may appear only as correlations between events in remote machines at remote times in the transform. Certain operations that don't matter in the long run may be skipped altogether. Yet the program is fundamentally unchanged. You know what's coming. If we thus transform a program that simulates a person, the person remains intact. Soul is in the mathematical equivalence, not in any particular detail of the process. It has a very etherial character. \sect{The Message is the Medium} If a mind can survive repeated radical restructurings, infusion into and out of different types of hardware and storage media, and is ultimately a mathematical abstraction, does it require hardware at all? Suppose the message describing a person is written in some static medium, like a book. A superintelligent being, or just a big computer, reading and understanding the message might be able to reason out the future evolution of the encoded person, not only under a particular set of experiences but also under various alternative circumstances. Existence in the thoughts of a beholder is no more abstract than as a transformed person-program described in the previous section, but it does introduce an interesting new twist. The superintelligent being has no obligation to accurately model every single detail of the beheld, and may well choose to skip the boring parts, to jump to conclusions that are obvious to it, and to lump together different alternatives it does not choose to distinguish. This looseness in the simulation can also allow some time reversed action - our superintelligent being may choose a conclusion then reason backwards, deciding what must have preceded it. Authors of fiction often take such liberties with their characters. The same parsimony of thought applies to the parts of the environment of the contemplated person that are themselves being contemplated. Applied a certain way, this parsimony will affect the evolution of the simulated person and his environment, and may thus be noticeable to him. Note that the subjective feelings of the simulated person are a part of the simulation, and with them the contemplated person feels as real in this implementation as in any other. It happens that quantum mechanics describes a world where unobserved events happen in all possible ways (another way of saying no decision is made as to which possibility occurs), and the superposition of all these possibilities itself has observable effects. The connection of this observation with those of the previous paragraph leads us into murky philosophical waters. To get even muddier, seriously consider the title of this section. If the subjective feelings of a person are part of the person-message, and if the evolution of the message is implicit in the message itself, then aren't the future experiences of the person implicit in the message? And wouldn't this mere mathematical existence feel the same to the person encoded as a more substantial simulation? I don't think this is mere sophistry, but I'm not prepared to take it any further for now. \sect{Immortality and Impermanence} Wading back into the shallows, let's examine a certain dilemma of existence, presently overshadowed by the issue of personal death, that will be paramount when practical immortality is achieved. It's this: in the long run survival requires change in directions not of your own choosing. Standards escalate with the growth of the inevitable competitors and predators for each niche. In a kind of cosmic Olympic games the universe molds its occupants towards its own distant and mysterious specifications. An immortal cannot hope to survive unchanged, only to maintain a limited continuity over the short run. Personal death differs from this inevitability only in its relative abruptness. Viewed on a larger scale we are already immortal, as we have been since the dawn of life. Our genes and our culture pass continuously from one generation to the next, subject only to incremental alterations to meet the continuous demand for new world records in the cosmic games. In the very long run the ancestral individual is always doomed as its heritage is nibbled away to meet short term demands. It slowly mutates into other forms that could have been reached from a range of starting points; the ultimate in convergent evolution. It's by this reasoning that I concle that it makes no ultimate difference whether our machines carry forward our heritage on their own, or in partnership with direct transcriptions of ourselves. Assuming long term survival either way, the end results should be indistinguishable, shaped by the universe and not by ourselves. Since change is inevitable, I think we should embrace rather than retard it. By so doing we improve our day to day survival odds, discover interesting surprises sooner, and are more prepared to face any competition. The cost is faster erosion of our present constitution. All development can be interpreted as incremental death and new birth, but some of the fast lane options make this especially obvious, for instance the possibility of dropping parts of one's memory and personality in favor of another's. Fully exploited, this process results in transient individuals constituted from a communal pool of personality traits. Sexual populations are effective in part because they create new genetic individuals in very much this way. As with sexual reproduction, the memory pool requires dissolution as well as creation to be effective. So personal death is not banished, but it does lose its poignancy because death by submergence into the memory pool is reversible in the short run. \sect{Back to Time Travel} In the continuing struggle for survival, we've already acquired considerable control of time. Memory - genetic, reflecting our evolution, nervous, storing our experiences, or artificial, recording events and thoughts, gives us some mastery the past. What of the future? A hallmark of intelligence is the ability to choose, from many possibilities, those actions that accomplish certain ends. In advanced robots, as in large brained animals, there is the possibility of deliberation, in which alternatives are imagined and their outcomes weighed, prior to the action. However imperfectly, such planning involves a prediction of the future, or, more precisely, of possible futures. The central goal of scientific inquiry has been the refinement of this skill. A good theory {\it predicts}. Theories and their predictions come to life in simulations, particularly on powerful computers. Such simulations have been especially accurate in the programs that predict the course of the planets and of spacecraft. More dramatically, if less accurately, modern weather programs simulate the action of the atmosphere over the entire globe. Increasingly powerful computation makes possible more accurate and longer range predictions. In a real sense powerful simulators are time machines, giving peeks into possible futures, and thus the power to choose among them. The laws of physics are quite symmetric in time, and simulations can usually be run in reverse as well as forward, and used to ``predict'' the past, perhaps guided by old measurements or archeological data. As with future predictions, any uncertainty in the initial measurements, or in the rule that evolves the initial state, will allow for a variety of possible outcomes. If the simulation is detailed enough, and is given all available information, then all of its "predictions" are valid - {\it any of the possible pasts may have led to the present situation}. This is a strange idea if you are accustomed to looking at the world in a strictly deterministic, Newtonian, way. Interestingly it closely resembles the uncertain world described by Quantum Mechanics, and perhaps hints at a mechanism underlying our world. Now, imagine an immense simulator that is able to model the whole surface of the earth on an atomic scale, and that can run time forward and back, and produce different plausible outcomes by making different random choices at key points in its calculation. Because of the great detail this simulator models living things, including humans, in their full complexity. By the arguments above such simulated people would be as real as you or I, though imprisoned in the simulator. We could join them by linking up with the simulation through a telepresence interface, that connects a ``puppet'' deep inside the simulation with a physical ``helmet'' and "gloves" outside, allowing us to experience the puppet's sensory environment, and to naturally control its actions. More radically, we could ``download'' our minds directly into a body in the simulation, and ``upload'' back into the real world when our mission is accomplished. Alternatively, we could bring people out of the simulation by reversing the process, linking their minds to an outside robot body, or uploading them directly into it. In all cases we would have the opportunity to recreate the past, and to some extent the future, and interact with it in a real and direct way. Realistically simulating the future is more difficult because archeology cannot help, and because an advancing culture will produce fundamental new knowledge, not found in the model, by research into new physical arenas or exploration of new geography. The same techniques, of course, allow visits to entirely novel situations and universes. \end{document}